Why idealism is right
If there is a God, it is not necessary that he follows such laws. This also reminds me of those that deny we have free will itself handily dismissing it an an illusion. Well, what is to stop me calling that an illusion of an illusion. We can only be conscious of all our theories, well, through our consciousness. In this sense I am sympathetic to Berkeleys attempts to try and hang a theory together on its productswhich even if you refute, well, you are using this consciousness to do?!
But sure, at the end of the day, I am unpersuaded to the extent B takes his theory but do think it ought to give pause for thought to those who dont wonder a little more at consciousness itslef, further upstream so to speak than the scientism that obsesses modern culture.. Kind of right at the beginning. Now I actually find the various versions of idealism fascinating from ancient Greek pantheism to Advaita Vedanta. What is it? Where is it? How does it work?
What is it made of? Who created it? Who created that creator? So I think Berkeley raises or discusses great philosophical ideas but he is really a religious apologist using philosophy to justify and prop up theology. He wants to take the real questions off the table so to speak for what seems to be religious reasons. And I actually liked that something nice was said about Descartes. It is easy to over look his great contributions to philosophy and science.
We might as well be in the Matrix or all be a computer simulation in the computer of an advanced alien race. Or all be holograms in their holodeck. But who made the computer programs? And where did they come from? The second millennium B. There are a number of proofs of this ideal world. The concepts of geometry, such as the concept of a circle, which is a line equidistant from a point, is something which does not exist in the physical world.
All physical circles, such as wheels, drawings, etc. Yet our mind has the concept of a perfect circle. Since this concept could not come from the physical world, it must come from an ideal world. Another proof is that from moral perfection. We can conceive of a morally perfect person, even though the people we know around us are not morally perfect. So where does someone get this idea of moral perfection?
Since it could not have been obtained from the world around us, it must have come from an ideal world. Platonism has been an extremely influential philosophy down through the centuries. George Berkeley was an Anglican bishop from Ireland who challenged the irrationality of the notion that matter exists autonomously outside the mind as Locke and other contemporaneous empiricists speculated. It is nonsensical and foolish to designate the causal qualities of humans, or spirits, to inert matter.
Only life forces, such as spirits or souls, are able to function causally through perception and are the only substances that really exist. Knowledge springs from perceptions, and because material objects are not causal agents, they unquestionably do not arouse perceptual activity.
Berkeley says that only an infinite being may produce and direct causally the perceptions that humans spirits have of physical matter. When he thinks of us, we are begotten and our existence activated. Yet, God still remains ineffable as he is beyond our comprehension. This process of self-determination is understood by Hegel as the way in which the Concept realizes itself.
After all, the Concept, being a thought-object or an object-thought itself, must also have reality or being and thus has to realize itself. In this way, Hegel does try to reconcile the need for conceptual elements constitutive of traditional epistemological idealism with most of the categorical commitments characteristic of traditional ontological idealism yet in a way that no longer requires the opposition between epistemology and ontology. Arthur Schopenhauer — heaped a great deal of invective on Fichte, Schelling, and Hegel.
For that reason, Schopenhauer is not always included among the German idealists. Nevertheless, since Schopenhauer works within a Kantian framework, and identifies underlying reality with pure activity, although of an arational rather than rational kind, it is useful to think of him within the framework of idealism. Schopenhauer puts forward his theory in his main work The World as Will and Representation Die Welt als Wille und Vorstellung , first published in December, with an date on its title page , and then in a much-expanded second edition in and yet another expanded edition in This book had been preceded by a doctoral dissertation On the Fourfold Root of the Principle of Sufficient Reason , which Schopenhauer subsequently regarded as the introduction to his magnum opus.
Schopenhauer holds that. This simple and perhaps inescapable thought may be regarded as the most fundamental epistemological motivation for any form of idealism. On the basis of this proposition, Schopenhauer then tries to distinguish his position from what he takes to be the skepticism of Hume, that there is a real question about whether there is either a subject or an object in addition to representations, and from the dogmatism of Fichte, that both of these can be proved; his own view as initially stated is rather that.
This intuition is not some phantasm derived from repeated experience; rather, it is something independent of experience, and to such an extent that experience must in fact be conceived as dependent on it, since the properties of time and space, as they are known a priori in intuition, apply to all experience as laws that it must always come out in accordance with. Schopenhauer also does not doubt that there is something other than the representing subject beyond what it represents, an underlying reality beginning with its own body as it is rather than as it merely appears.
We have immediate cognition of the thing in itself when it appears to us as our own body; but our cognition is only indirect when the thing in itself is objectified in other objects of intuition. What Schopenhauer means is that although we have an experience of our own bodies, as it were from the outside, through the same forms of space, time, and causality through which we experience all other bodies, including other animate bodies, and in this regard we experience all bodies including our own as mere appearance through the forms we impose on experience, we also have another experience, each of us of his or her own body, as it were from the inside, namely we have an experience of willing an action and of our bodies as the instruments of our wills, with no separation between will and action and thus no relevance of spatial separation, temporal succession, or difference between cause and effect.
However—and this is the argument of Book II—our immediate experience of our own bodies as instruments of our wills is an experience of our actions being immediately determined by desire rather than by reason. Trying to truly satisfy desire is the height of irrationality, but for Schopenhauer there is nothing else we can will—we can at best try to escape from the clutches of will altogether, whether through art, asceticism, or compassion.
But of course, if the underlying nature of reality, the thing in itself, is nothing other than will, then escape from its clutches should not really be possible but should at most be apparent. Ultimate reality, because, Schopenhauer assumes,. Schopenhauer devotes many pages to empirical descriptions of the similarities between the forces at work throughout the rest of nature and the merely apparently rational but really non-rational character of our own behavior, but of course the character of things in themselves cannot be inferred directly from any amount of empirical data; Schopenhauer derives his conclusion not from all this empirical illustration but rather from our allegedly immediate rather than empirical insight into the character of our own wills and the very problematic premise that at bottom everything is essentially one.
His position thus begins from an epistemological premise, namely that we can know ultimate reality through knowing ourselves, and reaches an ontological conclusion, that ultimate reality must be like ourselves, but in opposition to Kant and the other German idealists he assumes that our own nature is essentially non-rational and therefore that the ultimate character of reality, although it is in a certain sense like the mental, is also fundamentally non-rational.
It may seem far-fetched to think of Friedrich Nietzsche — as an idealist. After all, he presented himself as an almost fanatical anti-idealist throughout his life. A telling summary of his position concerning idealism is to be found in his letter to Malvida von Meysenburg 20 October :.
Considerations like these suggest that in spite of his protests, idealistic modes of thinking are not alien to Nietzsche. At least some of his beliefs are compatible with what has been called here epistemological arguments for idealism although Nietzsche himself would have taken these beliefs to express a form of realism. Philosophy in this traditional shape he took to be a somewhat enigmatic endeavor to pursue the mutually excluding tasks of culture-forming art and religion on the one hand and of cognition-focused science on the other see Nachgelassene Fragmente : Notebook 19, [47], [62], []; KSA 7.
It is doomed to failure because of two fundamental shortcomings. The first is that it gives a privileged status to truth in declaring truth to be the ultimate goal at which it aims.
This preoccupation with truth is based on the implicit assumption that truth has some overriding value. This assumption has never been justified, not even addressed by any philosopher. Nietzsche writes in the Genealogy of Morals Section 24 :.
Turn to the most ancient and most modern philosophies: all of them lack a consciousness of the extent to which the will to truth itself needs a justification, here is a gap in every philosophy—where does it come from? Because the ascetic ideal has so far been lord over all philosophy, because truth was set as being, as god, as the highest authority itself, because truth was not allowed to be a problem.
KSA 5. It is the tendency of philosophers to deny the obvious, to neglect surfaces in favor of what is allegedly behind them, out of habitual weakness and anxiety to prefer the stable and immutable over and against change and becoming.
This critical sentiment Nietzsche expresses quite often at different places in many of his published and unpublished writings. A nice example is the following note:. On the psychology of metaphysics.
This world is apparent—consequently there is a true world. This world is conditioned—consequently there is an unconditioned world. This world is full of contradiction—consequently there is a world free from contradiction.
This world is becoming—consequently there is an existing [ seiende ] world. All false inferences blind trust in reason: if A is, there must be its opposing concept B. It is suffering that inspires these inferences: at bottom there are wishes that such a world might be; similarly hatred of a world that causes suffering expresses itself through the imagination of another world, one full of value: the ressentiment of the metaphysicians against the actual world is here creative.
Notebook 8 [2]; reprinted in KSA Yet Nietzsche seems undecided how to evaluate the real motives that led Plato to his idealism.
Sometimes he wants to distinguish Plato from other idealists by crediting him with some obscure positive reason for endorsing idealism. In sum: all philosophical idealism until now was something like an illness, except where, as in the case of Plato, it was the caution of an overabundant and dangerous health, the fear of overpowerful senses, the shrewdness of a shrewd Socratic.
KSA 3. His ultimate verdict on metaphysics in all its ancient and modern forms is nicely expressed in the following note:. The influence of fearfulness. What has been most feared, the cause of the most powerful suffering the lust for domination, sexual lust, etc.
Thus they have step by step wiped out the affects—claimed God to be the opposite of the evil, i. Likewise they hate the irrational, the arbitrary, the accidental as the cause of countless physical suffering. In the same way they fear change, transitoriness: therein is expressed an oppressed soul, full of mistrust and bad experience The case of Spinoza: an inverted sort of person would count this change as charming. A playful being overladen with power would call precisely the affects, unreason and change good in an eudaimonistic sense, together with their consequences, with danger, contrast, dissolution, etc..
KSA This Nietzschean view can give rise to the impression that in the end he might have been closer to endorsing some form of epistemologically motivated idealism.
This leads to the topics of perspectivism and interpretation Auslegung in Nietzsche. Although the details are far from clear, the general tendency of his perspectivism is expressed quite well in aphorism from The Gay Science :. This view, according to which, further, the world each of us is experiencing is the product of an interpretation forced on us by some unconscious overriding drive Trieb that is the formative mark of the individual character of each of us, might be seen as endorsing a version of idealism if, as it is here, idealism is understood as the claim that what appears to be known as it is independent of the mind is in the end inescapably marked by the creative, formative, constructive activities of human mind, whether individual or collective.
However, it is far from clear whether Nietzsche wants us to think of this process of interpretation which leads to a specific perspective as a mind-dependent activity. Sometimes it seems as if he is favoring a quasi-Humean view according to which the intellect operates in the service of some anonymous affective and emotional drives in such a way that it just provides a set of necessary means to consciously realize what drives force us to do. The following note, for example, points in this direction:.
It is our needs that interpret the world: our drives and their to and fro. Every drive is a kind of domination, every one has its perspective, which it would force on all other drives as a norm. Notebook 7 [60]. In other passages Nietzsche seems to be more in line with a by and large Kantian view according to which the intellect provides some rules of transformation of what is given by the senses as individual and discrete data into more general representations.
Thus we find him claiming in section of The Gay Science :. This is what I understand to be true phenomenalism and perspectivism: that due to the nature of animal consciousness , the world of which we can become conscious is merely a surface- and sign-world, a world turned into generalities and thereby debased to its lowest common denominator,—that everything that enters consciousness thereby becomes superficial, thin, relatively stupid, general, a sign, a mark of the herd, that all becoming-conscious involves a vast and fundamental corruption, falsification, superficialization, and generalization.
Be this as it may, at least as far as epistemological idealism is concerned it is by no means obvious that either his explicit criticism of idealism or his remarks on the ways we make up epistemic worlds prevent Nietzsche from coming close to an idealist position himself. This is so because in epistemology his main enemy does not seem to be idealism but all forms of realism.
Although his epistemology does not explicitly imply any ontological claims, one could be tempted to see Nietzsche as toying with some ontologically idealistic fantasies. His speculations concerning the will to power as the ultimate dynamic foundation of all reality fall into this category.
For example,. Perspectivism is only a complex form of specificity[. And the process goes on…. Notebook 14 []. Thus, in the end there are no real obstacles to thinking of Nietzsche as an idealist on ontological as well as epistemological grounds, although the speculations that lead him in the former direction may be separable from the latter. Although it goes beyond the scope of this article, some hints about the fate of idealism in Germany might be appropriate. Interest especially in metaphysical versions of idealism waned in Germany in the second half of the nineteenth century and the first decades of the twentieth although it remained lively in other parts of Europe, e.
The decline of interest in idealism during this period had to do primarily with a certain aversion against what was taken to have been an excessive and extravagant usurpation of all fields of intellectual discourse by the classical German philosophers under the pretext of idealism.
This line of criticism was voiced most forcefully by influential natural scientists like Hermann von Helmholtz. Marginalization of idealism in these years also was an effect of the rise of Neo-Kantianism, which at least partly came into being both in its Marburg-school Hermann Cohen, Paul Natorp, Ernst Cassirer and in its Southwest Heidelberg -school Wilhelm Windelband, Heinrich Rickert, Emil Lask version as a reaction against the German idealists.
Although insofar as Neo-Kantianism was a reaction mainly to absolute idealism it could not entirely reject epistemological arguments of the kind that had traditionally led to idealism, especially in its Kantian variety. In particular, the writings of Friedrich Adolf Trendelenburg — and Rudolf Hermann Lotze — are documents of a lasting influence of idealistic figures and practices of thought, as was highlighted in detail by Beiser It also has to be kept in mind that during this period there were still active right old and left new Hegelians who were either critically or apologetically committed to a broadly Hegelian or idealistic framework in philosophy.
All these voices had some impact on philosophical discussions mainly about religion e. In spite of all this, it is fair to say that idealism fell out of fashion in the German speaking world, and has stayed that way.
Things were different in the English-speaking world, where idealism became an important topic in a wide spectrum of philosophical discussions ranging from metaphysics via aesthetics to moral and social theories. In England, Scotland, and Wales an idealism that was ultimately both epistemological and ontological in motivation became the dominant approach to philosophy for several decades, while in the United States idealism could not monopolize philosophy, having to share the stage with and ultimately reach an accommodation with pragmatism, but it nevertheless also flourished for several decades.
In fact, these philosophers were more willing to call themselves idealists than had been the earlier German idealists who supposedly inspired them, but who as has been argued were just as interested in escaping as in accepting the label. This is shown most tellingly insofar as their approach to a defense of idealism goes back to a state of the discussion characteristic of the period prior to Hegel and German idealism in general, rather connecting more directly to an understanding of idealism influenced by eighteenth-century disputes in the wake of Berkeley.
None of these figures except perhaps Royce continued to explore a dynamic conception of idealism distinctive of Hegel and the other German idealists—Royce in fact wrote more extensively and insightfully on Hegel and his immediate predecessors than any of the others with the exception of McTaggart. These philosophers were thus more willing to identify themselves as idealists than had been their predecessors.
However, these philosophers were not all equally monists. But both Green at the beginning of the movement and Royce towards its end strove for more nuanced positions, not excluding the existence of matter from their idealisms, and thus resisted monism.
For the most part, however, after the attacks on Bradley and Royce, explicit avowal of idealism became rare, with a few exceptions such as the prominent defense of idealism by Brand Blanshard in the s and less prominent defenses by Timothy Sprigge and John Foster in the early s. Thomas Hill Green —82 was the first of the great Oxford idealists. He is best remembered for a lengthy polemic with Hume that he published in the form of an introduction to a collected edition of Hume that he co-edited and for his posthumously published Prolegomena to Ethics , which is a polemic against utilitarianism from the point of view of a perfectionism inspired by Kant as well as by Hegel.
Green also left behind a set of Lectures on the Principles of Political Obligation that form one of the crucial documents of the political and social philosophy of British idealism and of idealism in the broadest sense mentioned at the outset of this entry. First, and here also much influenced by Kant, he argues that knowledge never consists in the mere apprehension of discrete items, but in the recognition of order or relation, and that such order or relation is not given but is constituted by and in consciousness.
Prolegomena , Francis Herbert Bradley — , however, argued for a more exclusive spiritualism, or an idealist ontology. Bradley presents his metaphysical views on the constitution and the main characteristics of reality most explicitly in Appearance and Reality: A Metaphysical Essay, which was first published in and reprinted many times during his lifetime.
He substantiates this claim by examining a range of central concepts from metaphysics and epistemology, among them the concepts of primary and secondary qualities, of substance and attribute, of quality and relation, space and time, of causality as well as the concept of a thing and that of the self.
The best known of his destructive arguments against these conceptions is that against qualities and relations because it played a role in the discussion that arose at the turn of the twentieth century between Bradley, Russell and Moore among others about the logical and ontological status of relations, i.
As to qualities and relations Bradley claims:. The arrangement of given facts into relations and qualities may be necessary in practice, but it is theoretically unintelligible. The reality, so characterized, is not true reality, but is appearance.
This is so because in order to be qualities they have to differ from other qualities and hence have to be distinct. However, without relations they could not be distinct. But distinctiveness presupposes plurality and plurality relations. Their plurality depends on relation, and, without that relation, they are not distinct. But, if not distinct, then not different, and therefore not qualities.
The same holds, according to Bradley, from the side of relations. Bradley summarizes as the result:. The conclusion to which I am brought is that a relational way of thought—any one that moves by the machinery of terms and relations—must give appearance, and not truth.
The result of his examination not just of the concepts of quality and relation but of all the other concepts he deals with consists in the verdict that all attempts to capture the true nature of reality in terms of these categories are futile because all these concepts are unintelligible, inconsistent and in the end self-contradictory. This means that what is designated by means of them cannot be real, but can only reflect the way the world appears to us, not the way it really is.
However, to be just appearance is not to be unreal in the sense of an illusion. But does this ontological argument for idealism exclude epistemology altogether? That is, since appearance always proves to be an inadequate way in which reality is present to us, is it beyond our means ever to become acquainted with the true essence of ultimate reality or can we avoid skepticism and claim that it is indeed possible for us to have access to the constitutive nature of reality? Bradley emphatically endorses the latter possibility.
According to him, the self-contradictoriness of what is appearance already implies that there is positive knowledge of reality: reality has to be One in the sense that it does not allow discord and it must be such that it can include diversity cf. This character of reality as an internally diversified individual system is revealed to us in sentient experience. The material basis of sentient experience is exhausted in feeling, thought, and volition.
Thus reality consists in what has to be taken as the undifferentiated unity of these modes of sentient experience before these modes make their appearance as different aspects of experience. This leads Bradley to assume that what is ultimately real is just what gives rise to appearances where appearances have to be understood as specific forms under which the underlying undifferentiated unity appears in each of these different aspects of experience.
In his words:. The identification of idealism with spiritualism, thus again an ontological interpretation of idealism, is most explicit in the works of John McTaggart Ellis McTaggart — The progress of an idealistic philosophy may, from some points of view, be divided into three stages. The problem of the first is to prove that reality is not exclusively matter. The problem of the second is to prove that reality is exclusively spirit.
The problem of the third is to determine what is the fundamental nature of spirit. He takes spirit to be the sum total of individual spirits or selves connected by the relation of love and bases this conviction on the claim that only this conception of what ultimate reality consists in allows us to overcome unavoidable contradictions connected with all other attempts to reconcile unity and diversity as the distinguishing marks of reality.
Harmony between unity and diversity can be established only on the basis of an all-encompassing relation of love between all the characteristic elements of reality, which in turn presupposes thinking of ultimate reality as a community of spirits or as Spirit. The Divine Shape Shifter. Sartre's Existentialism. Life and Death in Prison. The Examined Year: - Uncut. Good, Evil, and the Divine Plan.
Two Concepts of Safe Space. Self and Self-Presentation. Gun violence, advocacy, and the NRA. Perception, Memory, and Justice. The Demands of Morality. Will Innovation Kill Us? A Nietzschean Defense of Ben Carson. Collective Immortality: Living on Through Others. What is Cultural Appropriation?
The Logic of Regret. Social media, knowledge of others, and self-knoweldge. Bioethics — Myths and Realities.
Dance as a Way of Knowing. Technological Immortality. What is a Culture of Victimhood? The Changing Face of Feminism. Ashley Madison, accommodation, and silencing. The Ethics of Drone Warfare. Has Science Replaced Philosophy? Education and the Culture Wars. Are Some People Better than Others? The Last "Universal Genius". The Fine-Tuning Argument for God. Does Science Advance? The Power and Perils of Satire.
Does Neuroscience Threaten Free Will? The Ethics of Whistleblowing. Science and Politics: Friends or Foes? The Paradoxes of Ideology. Why Propaganda Matters. Unconditional Love. When Democracies Torture. The Bone that Changed China. A new multi-level hierarchy of ethics and morality. The Nature of Wilderness. The McDonalds-ification of Education. Democracy in Crisis. Forbidden Words. Ethical Relativism.
Disorders of the Mind - The Philosophy of Psychiatry. The More Good the Better? Camus and Absurdity. The Evolution of Storytelling. Political Activism in the Digital Age. The Psychology of Climate Change Denial. Regulating Bodies. Food Justice. Could Race be in Your Genes? Categorizing Humans. December The Sex Trade. Violating the Humanity of Others. Gut Feelings. Immortality: Hume and Boswell.
The Moral Costs of Climate Change. Transformative Experiences. Identities Lost and Found in a Global Age. Intuitions Are a Guide to…Look Here! The Fairness Fixation. Philosophy as Therapy. Freedom, Blame, and Resentment. Corporations and the Future of Democracy.
Second-Guessing Ourselves. Babies and the Birth of Morality. Neuroscience and the Law. Is Intuition a Guide to Truth? Remixing Reality: Art and Literature for the 21st Century. The Race Delusion. Privacy and The New Surveillance Society.
Tainted by the Sins of Our Fathers? Anatomy of a Terrorist. The Problem of Other Minds. Being Human is Like Being Here. The Reality of Time. The Metaphysics of Color. Risk and Rationality. Conspiracy Theories. Weapons of Mass Destruction. Acting Together. Science and Gender. Inspiration for Evil. The Legacy of Freud. Memory and the Self. Moral Luck. An Anti-Determinist Argument. Confessions of a Conflicted Carnivore. The Ethics of Soda. Tennis as a Way of Knowing.
A New Wrinkle on an Old Problem. The Dark Side of Science. Latin-American Philosophy. Diogenes the Cynic. Richard Fletcher, Historian. My Discovery of the X-Files. Science, Philosophy, and Theology. The George W. Bush Presidential Library and Museum.
Teaching Philosophy. What is philosophy? The Psychology of Partisan Politics. The Self. The Linguistics of Name Calling. December Turbo-charging the Mind. How Fiction Shapes Us.
Economics: Cult or Science? Mind Reading. Poetry As a Way of Knowing. Epicurus and the Good Life. On Being Normal. The Dionysus Awards. Black Solidarity. The Right to Privacy.
Philosophy in Fiction. Is Democracy a Universal Value? The Examined Year: December Nihilism and Meaning. What would Jesus do? A Blog for Christmas. Is it wrong to wreck the earth? To Forgive and Forget.
The Military: What is it Good for? Is Nothing Sacred Anymore? Thinking Inside the Box. Cooperation and Conflict. From the Minds of Babies. Morality and the Self. War, Sacrifice, and the Media. Deconstructing the College Admissions Rat Race. Schizophrenia and the mind. Health Care — is it a right or a privilege.
Time, Space, and Quantum Mechanics. The State of Public Philosophy. Philosophy and Everyday Life. What Are Words Worth? Atheism and the Well-Lived Life. Lincoln as a Philosopher. The Language of Responsibility. Gay Pride and Prejudice. Summer Reading The Prison System. Beliefs Gone Wild. Cities, Gentrification, and Inequality. Should Marriage Be Abolished? The Extended Mind. What is an adult? Social Networking. Is it All Just Relative?
Free Will. John Locke. A dialogue on Biracial Identity. Different Cultures, Different Selves. Derrida and Deconstruction. The Moral Costs of Markets. December The Philosophy of History.
Nominations open for the Third Annual Dionysus Awards! Children as Philosophers. The Power of Thought. Reading, Narrative, and the Self. Civil Disobedience. Levels of Reality. The Idea of a University.
Comments Will be Moderated, beginning immediately. The Occult Philosophy. Bargaining with the devil. Digital Selves. The terror of death, and how to overcome it. Gandhi as Philosopher. Philosophy for the Young: Corrupting or Empowering?
Self Deception. Bodies for Sale. William James. William James and the Squirrel Example. Social Reality. The Irrationality of Human Decision Making. Rawls on Justice. Democracy and the Press. What are Human Rights? Corporations as Persons. Psychological vs. Biological Altruism. Hannah Arendt. Culture and Mental Illness.
Faces, Feelings and Lies. The Ethics of Torture. On Being a Wife. What is a Wife? Food and Philosophy: Live at the Marsh. Science and Pseudo-science. What is Normal. Infinity: A Dialogue. The Second Annual Dionysus Awards. New Blog Policy. The Philosophical Legacy of Charles Darwin. Does Postmodernism Mean Moral Relativism? Am I a Postmodernist. Work and the Self. Comment on Pornography by Rae Langton. Pornography: Open Thread. Philosophical Wife Swapping.
Two Skeptical Arguments. The Place of Scepticism and Sceptical Arguments. Thoughts on the Reader. The Dionysus Awards: Join in the Fun. Philosophy Talk and the Paradoxical Facebook Contest. The First Annual Dionysus Awards. Philosophy and history.
December Rawls. Welcome Valley Public Radio Listeners. Why not buy and sell kidneys? Legal Ethics. Emergence: Live Blogging. Separation of Powers and the Charismatic Presidency. Dualism Strikes Back? More on the Luck of the Draw. The Luck of the Draw: Live Blogging! Philosophy and Film: Live Blogging. Open Thread on Apologies.
Saint Augustine. Why Music Matters: Open Thread! December Rename that Radio Show?? Political Correctness and the Speech Fashion War. What We've Been Up To, lately! Poetry, Philosophy, Truth. Why we Charge for Downloads. Suscribe to the Phiosophy Talk Download Service!!
Playful Intentions and the Problem of the Hypno-Flirt. Flirting as a two-step dance. Where Does Morality Come From? Check us out Wednesday and Thursday in Portland. What's on your Summer Reading list?
0コメント